https://www.project-syndicate.org/onpoint/veblen-keynes-hirschman-biographies-economics-outsiders-by-robert-skidelsky-2021-11
More
than Economists
Nov 12, 2021ROBERT
SKIDELSKY
While
systematic thinkers close a subject, leaving their followers with “normal”
science to fill up the learned journals, fertile ones open their disciplines to
critical scrutiny, for which they rarely get credit. Three recent biographies
show how this has been the fate of three great economists who were marginalized
by their profession.
- Jeremy Adelman, Worldly Philosopher: The
Odyssey of Albert O. Hirschman, Princeton
University Press, 2013.
Charles Camic, Veblen: The Making of an Economist Who Unmade Economics, Harvard University Press, 2020.
Zachary D. Carter, The Price of Peace: Money, Democracy, and the Life of John Maynard Keynes, Random House, 2020.
LONDON –
There are two types of extraordinary economist. The first type includes
pioneers of the field such as David Ricardo, William Stanley Jevons, and,
in our own time, Robert Lucas. They all aimed to economize knowledge
in order to explain the largest possible amount of behavior with the
smallest possible number of variables.
The second
category, which includes Thorstein Veblen, John Maynard Keynes, and Albert O.
Hirschman, sought to broaden economic knowledge in order
to understand motives and norms of behavior excluded by mainstream
analysis but important in real life. The first type of economist is
fiercely exclusive; the second has tried, largely in vain, to make
economics more inclusive.
The first
type of economist rather than the second has come to define the
field, owing partly to the successful drive to
professionalize the production of knowledge. Economics and other
social sciences are heirs of the medieval guilds, each jealously
preserving its chosen method of creating intellectual products. It also
reflects the increasing difficulty in a secular age of developing moral content
for the social sciences in general. We lack an agreed standpoint from outside
“the science” by which to judge the value of human activity.
And yet
Veblen, Keynes, and Hirschman are deservedly the subjects of three
recent biographies. Following Richard Parker’s excellent 2005 life of John Kenneth Galbraith, these works help
us understand how towering thinkers can be defined out of their
discipline.
REBEL WITH (AND WITHOUT) A CAUSE
Charles
Camic’s Veblen is a somewhat perplexing book, heavy on
sociological theory and light on biographical insight. Camic is so keen to make
Veblen a case study in the sociology of “knowledge production” that he misses
the oddball character of Veblen’s genius.
Veblen’s life
(he was born in 1857 and died 1929) spanned the shift in American capitalism
from small-scale individual proprietorship to large agglomerations of
concentrated power in agriculture, industry, and finance, accompanied by
an explosion of consumption and severe fluctuations in business activity.
The fluid state of economics in this era partly reflected these seismic social
shifts. The discipline was divided into rival schools – cost of production
battled subjective utility in theories of value; historical and
institutional economics flourished. Veblen, says Camic, was an iconoclast
not because he was an outsider, but because, in an “age of iconoclasm,” he was
an insider. This is neat, but it hardly explains the unique character of
Veblen’s iconoclasm or his failure to gain professional recognition.
The best place
to start is Milwaukee. Veblen’s parents emigrated to the United States
from Norway in 1847, owing to a shortage of land, and began to farm in
Wisconsin. By the time Veblen was born, they owned a 200-acre (81-hectare)
self-supporting farmstead. They were skilled craftspeople. His father
built their house, and his mother made their clothes. Veblen was brought
up in the Lutheran faith of hard work and frugality: nothing was
wasted. There was a strong sense of community built on common worship,
and a marked respect for “useful” knowledge – in contrast to the study of dead
languages, which, Veblen would later write, merely served the “decorative ends
of the leisure class.” Veblen’s crucial distinction between production and
waste, and between virtuous and predatory capitalism, has its roots in his
austere upbringing.
In the
stylized picture of his youth that Veblen later reproduced in his work, the
productive classes created wealth while the rich wasted it, and thus
delayed the satisfaction of society’s real needs. This interpretation
of the capitalist economy ran contrary to the classical and
neoclassical economics of the day, which assumed efficient use of all
available resources. It was to find incomparable expression in the two books
for which Veblen is best known: The Theory of the Leisure Class (1899) and The Theory of Business
Enterprise (1904).
WASTE AND WANT
In The
Theory of the Leisure Class, Veblen aimed to develop a model of waste that
would overturn the marginalist theory of distribution. According to
Camic, this book made three surgical cuts in the corpus of
marginalist economics. First, the value of products derives not from their
marginal utility to individual consumers but from their social function as
signifiers of wealth. Purchasers were engaged in a never-ending game of
“invidious comparison,” involving everything from high-priced clothing and
ornate dinnerware to exotic gardens and grotesque breeds of pets. “Conspicuous
abstention […] from all useful employment” was a further mark of “superior
pecuniary achievement,” expressed by men pursuing non-productive
occupations like warfare, politics, and law and by women dressing in clothes
that incapacitated them from “all useful exertion.”
Second,
Veblen attacked the assumption of universally valid laws. This was a
common position of Hirschman and Keynes as well, and, in the eyes of many, it
marked all three as inferior scientists. According to Veblen, the leisure class
was an institution that had developed in stages over many centuries in response
to environmental challenges. Economics, he wrote, should be “a
science of the evolution of economic institutions,” not the analysis
of static equilibria. It was foolish to imagine “a gang of Aleutian Islanders slushing about
in the wrack and the surf with rakes and magical incantations for the capture
for shell-fish [...] to be engaged on a feat of hedonistic equilibration in
rent, wages, and interest.”
Third, Veblen
argued, the unproductive classes acquire the wealth they need to support their
“conspicuous consumption” not by useful work, but by “predation.” One
of his central contentions was that the so-called robber barons of America’s
Gilded Age – the Carnegies, Vanderbilts, and Rockefellers – were direct
descendants of the pillaging barbarian chiefs of ancient times. His theory
of conspicuous consumption had a profound influence on sociological theory, as
well as on his foremost North American heir, Galbraith, another economist who
was more than an economist but regarded by his profession as less than one.
Veblen’s
second book, The Theory of Business Enterprise, developed the predation
theme further. As Camic shows, it reflected the controversies
caused by the growth of large corporations in their various organizational
forms, including cartels, trusts, and merged entities. Using the old
Aristotelian distinction between “making things” and “making money,” Veblen
highlighted the “industrial” activities of inventors, engineers, chemists and
mineralogists, mining experts, electricians, and skilled mechanics, which were
shaped by the “instinct for workmanship.” He contrasted these endeavors with
the “pecuniary” activities of business managers and entrepreneurs,
corporate promoters, speculators, bankers, stockbrokers, lawyers, and real
estate agents, which were driven by love of money. These groups were not
just intermediaries, as orthodox economists held, but “leeches” who sucked the
blood of producers.
THE LONELY ICONOCLAST
This brings
us to the Veblen problem: Why was the most original US economic mind of his era
a professional failure? Veblen never got tenure: two prestigious universities,
Chicago and Stanford, dismissed him for conducting extramarital
affairs. He subsequently languished in a junior position at the
then-backwater University of Missouri, before quitting academic life
altogether and living on handouts and journalism until his death.
Previous studies of Veblen by Joseph Dorfman and Daniel
Bell portray him as the archetypal outsider – an “academic
floater,” in Bell’s description – unable to establish solid academic links with
his profession. Camic, a sociology professor, rejects this
interpretation. Veblen, he says, was a thoroughly professional
economist who took advantage of an exceptionally fluid period in the discipline
to win space for his “variations” on orthodox themes. But this hardly justifies
the claim in the book’s title that Veblen upended economics, and does
nothing to explain his failure to win academic recognition. Camic wants to have
it both ways by portraying Veblen as someone who strayed from a system while
denying that there existed a system to stray from.
To do
biographical justice to Veblen would have required much more
attention to his personal style and circumstances. Camic is almost
blind to the connection between the originality of Veblen’s thought and his use
of words. His satirical language both signaled and disguised
his iconoclasm. This made it easy for economists to treat his thinking
as decorative rather than analytical. Like Galbraith, another famously
ironic economist, Veblen’s main influence was on non-economists. He was
marginal to his own profession.
Camic dutifully
records that owing to a “rare anatomical abnormality,” Veblen’s first
wife “was unable to have sexual intercourse,” but refused to give him a
divorce. This raises questions of mental health that Camic’s
method of applied sociology is ill-attuned to answer. What is clear is
that Veblen was regarded as something of a hick in the world of elite
US universities, and this bred a resentment that sharpened his perceptions but
made him a testy colleague. He hit back with a scathing 1918 attack on higher
education, The Higher Learning in America, which he initially subtitled A Study in
Total Depravity.
It is a sign
of Camic’s idiosyncratic treatment of his subject that he makes only one
fleeting mention of Veblen’s most important later work, The Engineers and the Price
System (1921).
Its concluding chapter, entitled “A Memorandum on a Practicable Soviet of
Technicians,” points to a future in which managers and engineers combine
into a “new class” of technicians, who will take over from the vested
interests of both capital and labor to guide the progress of industrial
evolution. The new class will become directors of society, ironing out its
“frictions” just as engineers iron out frictions in the production of
goods. Camic thus misses an opportunity to show how Veblen’s disgust
with capitalist civilization led him not to Marx but to St. Simon,
Comte, and Plato.
Veblen died
just before the start of the Great Depression. That calamity opened a new
chapter in the theory of waste, which we associate with Keynes. The
waste that Keynes discerned was caused not by inefficient distribution of
existing resources, but by insufficient utilization of potential resources
– making it a problem of demand instead of supply.
THE OUTSIDER INSIDER
Unlike
Veblen, Keynes was too important be expunged from the
economics profession. He was not only central as a policymaker, but, like
Adam Smith, offered a rare combination of intellectual fertility and
conclusiveness. Neither Smith nor Keynes presented formal models, but
bits of their work could readily be formalized. Ricardo did this for Smith, and
John Hicks did it for Keynes. But beyond Keynes’s “income-determination”
model lies a profusion of suggestive asides that leave
his thoughts open-ended.
Nevertheless, although
Keynes – unlike Veblen – really did upend economics (at least for a time),
the profession has persistently tended to belittle him as an economist and
narrow the importance of his contribution. He was not a “real” economist,
it is said, because he failed to understand the idea of a “budget
constraint.”
I prefer the
description of Keynes by his wife, the Russian ballerina Lydia Lopokova, who
called him “more than economist.” Keynes knew all about budget
constraints. His essential contribution was to point out that unmanaged
market economies normally operated well below full employment, thus
calling for a “general theory” in which full employment is only one of a number
of possible stable positions. Furthermore, these two types of
equilibria called for two types of economic policy, one suitable for
full employment and the other to address underemployment. A “full
investment” policy required the government to supplement private investment
sufficiently in a depression to achieve full employment.
These were
novel and thrilling insights that current talk about
the “natural rate of unemployment” and “V-shaped recoveries” from slumps
has all but obliterated. What has remained is Keynes’s memorable, mordant
phrasemaking, such as “in the long run, we are all dead,” “it is
better for reputation to fail conventionally than to succeed
unconventionally,” and “when statistics do not make sense, I find it generally
wiser to prefer sense to statistics.”
Keynes is the
subject of Zachary D. Carter’s The Price of Peace, a superb work of
political economy by a young financial journalist and scholar.
As its full title indicates, it is not primarily a biography, but rather a
study of Keynes’s impact on three topics, of which only one, money, is directly
connected with economics.
There is
almost nothing in the book about Keynes’s family and upbringing. This is a
shame, because they help explain his relative indifference to questions of
distribution, something that Keynesians are loath to acknowledge. “Escape was
possible for any man of capacity or character at all exceeding the average,
into the middle and upper classes,” he wrote in 1919, reflecting on his own
rise into the British establishment. Poverty was mainly caused by a stuttering
economic system, not by a skewed distribution of wealth or opportunity.
Carter is
right, though, to emphasize the influence of the conservative philosopher
Edmund Burke, and his doctrine of prudence, on Keynes’s intellectual
development. This, together with a “civil-service mind,” kept Keynes’s feet
firmly planted in the real world. Like the Greek philosopher Thales, he could
both gaze at the stars and make a killing in the wheat market.
ECONOMICS IN WAR AND PEACE
Although
Keynes’s economic theory, unlike Veblen’s, was reducible to a model that could
become the basis of policy, his purpose was nothing less than to save
civilization in an age of economic depression and war. “Keynes,”
Carter writes, “was a philosopher of war and peace, the last of the
Enlightenment intellectuals who pursued political theory, economics, and ethics
as a unified design.” This wider aspect of Keynes’s thinking was lost when
his ideas crossed the Atlantic to become the “New Economics” practiced in
the US from World War II until the 1970s.
The economics
part of this story is well known. Whereas Keynes made “underemployment
equilibrium” depend on inescapable uncertainty about the
future, leading US Keynesians like Paul Samuelson made it depend on sticky
wages and prices. This opened the door to stabilization policy while
eliminating the heart of Keynes’s theory, which was
mathematically intractable.
This
so-called “neoclassical synthesis” started to unravel in the late 1960s, when
the Keynesian framework came under attack for causing inflation,
leaving neoclassical theory as the only basis for policy. That was the cue for
the supply-siders, who aimed to unstick the sticky wages and prices through
labor-market reforms. Market-achieved equilibrium could now be plausibly
restated as a full-employment equilibrium, while independent central banks
would stop governments from being careless with the money supply. Milton Friedman replaced Keynes, and monetarism replaced
fiscal Keynesianism. None of this stopped the 2008 global financial crisis,
following which governments briefly resurrected Keynesian policy to bail out
insolvent banks.
In
Carter’s account of this counter-revolution, Friedrich von Hayek
rightly plays a larger role than he is generally credited with.
Whereas Friedman was essentially an extremely clever technician, Hayek was
the counter-revolution’s philosophic progenitor. It was Hayek who clung
resolutely to the view of economics as being exclusively concerned
with the study of scarcity. He didn’t believe it was possible to
democratize the elite; power, too, was a scarce resource.
Something new
to me in Carter’s book is the story of Hayek’s link with Harold
Luhnow, a half-mad home-furnishings magnate from Kansas City. Hayek’s 1944
book The Road to Serfdom struck the furniture tycoon like a clap
of thunder. He began dreaming of a world “in which clunky and corrupt
apparatuses of government might be replaced by the genius and generosity of the
wealthy.” Luhnow persuaded the University of Chicago to appoint Hayek as
Professor of Social Thought, and paid his salary. He helped him found the Mont
Pelerin Society, which became “the world’s preeminent right-wing intellectual
organ.” As Carter notes, “Luhnow’s financing changed academia.”
MILITARY KEYNESIANISM
But there was
something else. In his short 1930 essay Economic
Possibilities for our Grandchildren, Keynes
assumed that full-employment policy plus technical progress
would go on long enough to bring abundance within reach of all, and
thereby realize the ethical promise of the good life. In such a world,
what would remain would be the social problem of wealth and income
distribution.
It
was this leap into the future that enables Carter to write
that Keynes “reframed the central problem at the heart of economics as the
alleviation of inequality, pivoting away from the demands of production and the
incentives facing the rich and powerful.” In other words, once the
production problem was overcome, we would be back to the problem posed by
Veblen of how to prevent the waste of productive resources – not through
unemployment, but by business predators and the idle rich.
This distant
prospect was far from the center of Keynes’s concerns in the 1930s,
and there was no explicit warrant in the General Theory for
redistribution. So, those who had no desire for redistribution interpreted
Keynes’s theory as a simple case of demand deficiency, to be cured by any kind
of deficit spending. This opened the way to the capture of US Keynesianism by
the military-industrial complex. Keynesian ideas “which had been developed
explicitly to combat ‘militarism,’ became essential for the
maintenance of a permanently militarized world,” Carter writes. “The idealized
humanitarian aims of liberal imperialism that Keynes had admired as a young man
were refitted for an era of US hegemony.” Massive military spending was a
source of waste unimagined by Veblen, and ensured that scarcity, like the poor,
would always be with us.
With
capitalism’s triumph over communism after 1989, the rationale for military
Keynesianism declined. But this did not lead to the rehabilitation of civil
Keynesianism, because the intellectual battle had been lost. Carter ends
his book with a devastating critique of US President Bill Clinton’s
administration, which, at every opportunity, “transferred power from the
government to the financial markets,” building financial boom and bust into the
system. “The economic problem for humanity,” he writes, “is no longer a problem
of production but of distribution-inequality.”
How to solve
this problem remains a mystery. Keynes had always tried to steer a middle way
between reform and revolution, preservation and disruption. But “perhaps the
type of social change [Keynes] envisioned,” Carter concludes
gloomily, “can be achieved only through revolution [...] The greatest
American victories for democracy and equality [...] came at the end of a gun.”
THE WANDERER
With
Hirschman, the scenery shifts from the traumas of developed countries to those
of economic development. Although neither Veblen nor Keynes gave much thought
to the world’s poor and backward regions, development economics drew
inspiration from both. From Veblen came the distinction between productive and
wasteful activity and the need to transfer resources from the latter to
the former. Keynes’s idea of “underemployment” in industrial
countries was turned into the idea of “disguised unemployment” in
agricultural economies. As the late Canadian economist Harry Johnson put
it: “the notion that there exist masses of ‘disguised unemployed’ people leads
easily to the idea that ‘development’ involves merely the mobilization and
transfer of these presumably costless productive resources into economic
activities.”
Hirschman
rejected such “big push” theories of development in favor of micro-schemes
that would serve as learning platforms. Jeremy Adelman’s Worldly Philosopher is a superb
biography of an elusive thinker who was both less and more than an economist.
Hirschman was less than an economist because he never formally trained as
one. But he was also more because his thinking overflowed the boundaries set by
the formal sciences, while his mordant wit mocked their
scientific pretensions.
Adelman, a
historian at Princeton University, is attentive to how Hirschman’s
German-Jewish background influenced his character and thought. In 1933,
with Hitler having recently come to power, the 17-year-old Hirschman
left his family in Germany and became a lifelong wanderer. “With [his]
charm,” writes Adelman, “came a remarkable skill in deflecting personal
difficulties and avoiding trouble.” Hirschman became a master of concealment
and reinvention, and drew from his own history a Kafkaesque sense of
being caught in the vises of an insane system that insisted on its
rationality.
Hirschman’s
most famous book, Exit, Voice, and Loyalty (1970), reflected
the tensions in his own life “between leaving, fighting, and accepting.”
One might add that no thinker of German origin can altogether escape the
influence of dialectical reasoning, from which Anglo-American social science is
exempt. For Hirschman, economic outcomes were the result of
contradictions between politics and economics. He came to see
the treatment of political relations as the “intrusive” bane of
development economics.
DARING TO FAIL
Hirschman wanted
to create a “social economics” rooted in time, contingency, politics, and
institutions – a hopeless undertaking that would have abolished the discipline.
Works like Exit, Voice, and Loyalty and The Passions
and the Interests: Political Arguments for Capitalism Before its Triumph (1977)
are classics of social thought, but have had little impact on the profession. As
Adelman says, “what made Hirschman so influential beyond his discipline,
speaking as an economist to social scientists, is what deprived him of all
influence within it.”
Thus,
Hirschman was “marginal” to Columbia University, and his Harvard
University tenure was a “curio.” Like Veblen, he was a “catastrophically bad
teacher,” escaping from the chore with foundation grants. Hirschman is not
mentioned in Samuelson’s Economics (nine editions), nor in
David Begg, Stanley Fischer, and Rüdiger Dornbusch’s Economics (five editions), and
he is left out of the Oxford Dictionary of Economics. (Veblen
fares little better.)
Hirschman’s
work as a development economist challenged the hubris of experts from the
World Bank and other institutions who descended from the sky with briefcases
full of plans for abolishing poverty. He parodied their reasoning: “As long as
nature is in charge of mishaps like floods, they are acts of God; when men
undertake to remedy one of nature’s ills, this remedy is expected to cure all
ills.” In 1954, he established his own development consultancy in Bogotá,
Colombia. Its business was project assessment. The propensity to plan,
Hirschman said, should be replaced by the “propensity to experiment and
improvise.”
The subtext
of his first major book, The Strategy of Economic
Development (1958),
was, Adelman writes, a “critique of [...] the preference for abstract
model-building in the service of big all-encompassing plans of modernization
through top-down reform.” Policymakers should instead choose investment
projects that had good potential “linkages” to other economic activities.
Hirschman
accepted the risk of failure, but thought experimentation would create
“pressure points” for further advance. He came close to advocating projects he
thought likely to fail, in order to encourage popular protest to correct
their shortcomings. He invented the crucial idea of the “optimal”
crisis – deep enough to provoke change but not so deep that it wiped out the means
of achieving it. Creating problems to solve as a method of progress has a
distinctly Mephistophelian ring.
The
background to Exit, Voice, and Loyalty was the explosion
of the US counterculture in the 1960s. This stimulated Hirschman to
explore the different forms that discontent with institutions could take, using
the “consumer” as the stylized agent. His thesis was that consumers’
loyalty to commercial or political brands could no longer be taken for
granted. They could express their discontent in the form of exit/desertion (the
economist’s model of consumer choice) or voice/expression (the democratic form
of protest).
Hirschman’s
clear preference was for voice. In a famous example, he argued against
wealthy, articulate parents or patients exiting public school or health
systems for private provision, because this would ensure a downward spiral
in the quality of public education and health care. Instead, Hirschman
argued, they should campaign to improve public services for their families and
themselves, which would generate pressure for improvement for everyone.
But he never explained properly why they should do so. As some reviewers
pointed out, he lacked a theory of loyalty.
PASSION PLAY
Hirschman’s
most ambitious attempt at cross-disciplinary fertilization was The
Passions and the Interests. David Hume had written that “reason is,
and ought only to be the slave of the passions, and can never pretend to any
other office than to serve and obey them.” Constitutional checks were needed to
channel the destructive passions into the service of the common good. But
suppose the market could do so? Montesquieu had shown the way
by sagely remarking that while men’s passions may lead them astray,
their interest may impel them to cooperate with others. One
might even argue that it was the selfish passions that awakened reason
from its sleep. Adam Smith made this insight the foundation of political
economy.
Hirschman
brilliantly explained that by branding passions as interests, Smith
destroyed the ground of their conflict:
“In the early
modern age, man was widely viewed as the stage on which fierce and
unpredictable battles were found between reason and passion or, later, among
the various passions. At mid-eighteenth century, some hope was held out that
the interests, which were increasingly understood in the purely pecuniary sense
of the term, would be able to tame the disastrous, if aristocratic passions.
But by the latter part of the century, the passions were collapsed into the
interests by Adam Smith who pronounced the ‘great mob of mankind’ to be safely
programmed. From the cradle to the grave its members were to be exclusively
concerned with ‘bettering their condition.’”
In his later
years, Hirschman battled inconclusively with the problem of finding a place for
morality in the social sciences. His outlook became steadily gloomier as
neoliberalism became orthodoxy in both developed and developing
countries. His last book, The Rhetoric of Reaction:
Perversity, Futility, Jeopardy (1991), used the tripartite scheme of Exit, Voice, and
Loyalty to describe the different forms of rejection
of social democracy. But he remained a hopeful contrarian.
BEYOND ECONOMICS
Veblen,
Keynes, and Hirschman were more than economists because they practiced their
economics from a standpoint outside the profession, using it to criticize not
only the assumption of rational self-interest, but also the consequences
of economists’ indifference to “preferences.” Veblen’s standpoint
was explicitly religious; he was still of a believing generation. Keynes,
too, was an ethicist. G.E. Moore’s Principia Ethica remained
what he called his “religion under the surface.” Hirschman wanted a “moral
social science” that would be continually sensitive to the ethical content of
its analysis.
The problem
of moralizing economics in a secular age defeated all three. But their
efforts are not just part of the history of ideas. They also serve as a
rallying call to new generations of students.
These three
economists’ frequently mocking style was their way of establishing
their distance from their profession. Their irony was not ornamental but
actually shaped the substance of their arguments. This style limited their
impact on economics, but made them highly influential outside it, because
critics of economics sensed something transgressive about them.
For Veblen
and Hirschman, it was their refusal to take the bait of modeling which made
them less than economists in the eyes of the profession. This cannot be said of
Keynes. Not only did he have an impregnable base among economists, but he
bequeathed a theory that could be applied. Nevertheless, the power holders
in the profession (and outside it) marginalized him as soon as they felt
confident enough to do so. “Who are you?” wrote Keynes’s friend David Garnett
in 1915. “Only an intelligence that they need in their extremity [...] then
back you go into the bottle.”
Systematic
thinkers close a subject, leaving their followers with “normal” science to fill
up the learned journals. Fertile ones open up their disciplines to critical
scrutiny, for which they rarely get credit. This has been the fate of the
three great economists whose work – and enduring influence – these books
describe.
Writing for
PS since 2003
186 Commentaries
Follow
Robert Skidelsky, a member
of the British House of Lords, is Professor Emeritus of Political Economy at
Warwick University. The author of a three-volume biography of John Maynard
Keynes, he began his political career in the Labour party, became the
Conservative Party’s spokesman for Treasury affairs in the House of Lords, and
was eventually forced out of the Conservative Party for his opposition to
NATO’s intervention in Kosovo in 1999.
No hay comentarios.:
Publicar un comentario